THE
INDIAN CONCEPTS OF KNOWLEDGE AND SELF (Second instalment)
KALIDAS BHATTACHARYYA The [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] doctrines that mental
states are short-lived and that two or more such states cannot co-exit were
examined in the last section. We arrived at the following conclusions:
(i) There is no possible denial of mental states as emergent and cessant.(ii)
Their cessation is due to no foreign cause, they are self-destroying; and
continuation is not incompatible with self-destruction. (III) Co-existence
of two or more mental states
is not merely not impossible but often a fact. In the next section we propose
to examine in detail the [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] concept of Object. SECTION
III The concept of object examined A. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika concept
of Object reiterated [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] has distinguished between object
(visaya) and the real (padartha). A real becomes an object when it is known;
and as the content of a possible (not actual) knowledge, it is a possible
object. The real is that which as absolutely independent
of my present knowledge has only been revealed by it. When it is so revealed
(known) there occurs between it and the knowledge a relation which as belonging
to the real is called its objectivity (visayata), but as belonging at the
same time to the
knowledge it is subjectivity(visayita) of that knowledge. Objectivity, unless
it be only possible, is, in other words, and extrinsic relational property
accruing to the real when it is known. This concept of objectivity was elucidated
in further details
in Section I. In that Section it was also shown that this objectivity is
almost a tertiary property, in the sense that though it belongs to the real,
and not, as objectivity, to the knownledge of the real, it yet, as a relational
property, is constituted by that knowledge.
For a proper understanding of this two questions which were not raised in
Section I need here be examined. They are (i) whether the relation cannot
be extrinsic in the sense that it iss not constituted by either term, and
(ii) whether objectivity as aproperty
(relational or not ) may not be due to knowledge as an efficient (nimitta)
cause, not constituted by it. The reply to the first question would be thsi:
Relation may often be extrinsic in the sense indicated, but never so in
certain cases, particularly where it is between knowledge and the real that
is known. Between the world of knowledge and that of reals there is nothing
that is not included in either.
Hence the relation between an instance of knowledge and the real known must
belong to one of these worlds. As a matter of fact, it is found to belong
to either alternatively: Knowledge is of the real and the real is known.
In the former case the relation
belongs to knowledge, in the latter it belongs to the real. The relation
between knowledge and the real is not, in other words, a simple affair like
that between any two reals. It may be asked if the dichotomy of the knowledge-world
and the thing-world is metaphysically justified. Modern realists have questioned
this, and we are told that [Nyaya-vai'sesika] also does not allow this.
Is not knowledge known quite as much as other
things? Knowledge indeed is known like other things. Yet the knowledge
that is known is knowledge of a particular thing. No other thing is necessarily
of another thing. So far knowledge is fundamentally different from other
things. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] onlyinsists
that this type of thing is nevertheless revealed as an ordinary thing in
another knowledge and, as so revealed, is an object. Knowledge, in other
words, as necessarily of a thing, is necessarily subjective (visayin), and
yet there is no metaphysical
clash between this subjectivity and the objectivity (thinghood) of knowledge.
Included in the sweeping world of things there are two entirely different
types, viz., those which are necessarily subjective and those which are not
so. The distinction
between the two is more deep-seated than that between a tree and a blade
of grass. Neither the tree nor that grass is necessarily subjective. The
second question was whether knowledge to which objectivity is due is not
its efficient cause. Our reply is: it is not an efficient cause, it is constitutive.
The reasong is stated below: Objectivity, though a property of the real
known, is also the relation between that real and the knowledge. It is a
relation of the real to that knowledge. As of the real it belongs to the
real, but as a relation to that knowledge it is constituted by
the knowledge.
The real is here the locus (anuyogin) of the relation, and knowledge its
constitutive determinant (Pratigyogin). There is no mere relation, no relation
that is without a constitutive determinant. A further peculiarity of the
determinant
of a relation is that it is never a class, unless the relation is specifically
of a thing to a class. Object, from this point of view, may then be defined
as that real which has for a property a relation constitutively determined
by the knowledge ofthat
real. The real here is not constitute by knowledge, because the relation
in question is its extrinsic property. But objectivity and , therfore,
object also are constituted by knowledge. 'Constituted by knowledge' may
not mean that knowledge isan
[upandana karana], but there is no denying the fact that objectivity is somehow
constituted by knowledge. The very concept of object as the real that has
been known involves reference to knowledge. No effect, on the other hand,
involves in the very concept of itself reference to its efficient cause.
This also proves that knowledge is not efficient cause (but
constitutive of object). But though objectivity is constituted by knowledge
this does not mean that the total knowledge-situation is to be interpreted
idealistically. Objectivity belongs also to the real as its property, and
this real is independent of the knowledge that reveals
it. The reals as such are apprehended in non-judgmental perception (nirvikalpa-pratyaksa).
This, again, is not the only reason why [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] sides with realism.
There is another reason more fundamental. The fundamental postulate of
knowledge
is truly independent. Objectivity, though constituted by knowledge, appears
independent. Hence it is truly independent. The only way to reconcile this
independence with its being constituted by knowledge is to hold that the
independent is the real
as such and objectivity as consituted by knowledge belongs nevertheless to
thsi real. The postulate is not dogmatic. It is capable of some sort of
proor. If O appears independent of knowledge it is either really independent
or not. But the negative alternative is untenable. If it were not really
independent it was either the knowledge
itself or constructed by it. But it cannot be either. To no corrective
awareness is it ever felt that way. One cannot also insist that, whether
felt or not, it is inferred that way. The apparent objectivity of O would
go aganinst that inference. No
cognition ever appears independent of itself, and no cognitive construction
appears independent of the cognition that constructs it. it cannot be said,
again, that the independence is an illusion. The independence as such cannot
be an illusion. There
is no illusory content which, or the like of which, was never presented as
real. Object, then, is independent of the knowledge of it. This independence
of object is the same thing as the fact that objectivity belongs to the real
as a contingent property, which means that object being independent of knowledge
does not clash with its being constituted by knowledge. Even if this were
not
the case, but object or objectivity were understood as itself independent
of knowledge, even then there would be no grat difficulty. To be constituted
by knowledge would than, it is true, contradict is forced upon us, and there
is no way out, it has to
be submitted to. Such cases, however, ought not to be multiplied for the
mere luxury of specualtion. In spite, then, of being constituted by knowledge,
object or objectivity is real. But there is yet another difficulty to remove.
[Nyaya-Vai'sesika] has classified reals into severn original groups. But
object or objectivity appears to belong to none
of them. Forms of objectivity, ivz. [vi'sesyata], [Prakarata], etc., and
therefore object also, are neither [dravya] nor [guna] nor [karma] nor [samanya],
[samavaya], [vi'sesa] or [abhava]. If they do not belong to any of these
they ought not to be called
real. This is the difficulty. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] has removed it in two
ways. Most objects and there for also the forms of objectivity involved
are the [svarupa] of reals; and some objects, particularly those which are
flase, are only to bee analysed into real consituents where theform
of objectivity is not substantive-adjective [samanadhi-karanya], but only
[samsarga]. What is meant is that the total object of illusion is only a
loose unity. To explaing. An Object as the content of knowledge is always
a complex unity. The elements of this unity are reals (Padarthas) which
as such are knowable in [nirvikalpa-Pratyaksa] only, and the relations that
are added in [savikalpa] knowledge are, as
seen, both knowledge-wise
and reality-wise. As reality-wise they are taken as real, and unless contradicted
they are also really real. The elements and the relation are thus equally
real. If the relations cannot be places among the catalogued [Padarthas],
this is because these relations, though real, are not additional realities.
If a real A is really related to a real B, this does not necessarily mean
that the relation is a third real entitly. The Buddhists too have admitted
this when they hold that
[santana] which is as real as teh [Ksanikas] is yet not other than these.
Many Western thinkers also insist that relations, though really relating,
are not other than relata. All the difficulty arises when the reality of
relation is misunderstood as
its being a third entity. If it is not third, if, in other words, the real
relation is exhausted in the catalogued [Padarthas], there remains no difficulty
in admitting its reality. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] holds that the so-called additional
relation we are
aware of in [savikalpa-jnana] has this status only. They are exhausted in,
another name of which is that they are the [svarupa] of, the [padarthas]
they relate, not additional realities. Not that all entities which we call
relation are of this type. In herence (samavaya) and contact (samyoga) are
called relation and they are additional reals. Similaly when a fact or a
series of facts which are normally treated as terms (as oppposed to
relation) act as relation (e.g., between a father and a child) they, even
as relation, are additonal entities. The additionality of inherence and
contact follow from the fact that they are matters of [nirvikalpa-Pratyaksa],
and that of the facts or the
rseries is immediately evident. Where there is no such special reason or
immediate evidence a relation need not be additional. A flower, its red
colout and the inherence of the latter in the former are, according to [Nyaya-Vai'sesika],
separate reals; yet
in the perceptual judgment (savikalpa-Pratyaksa) of the form 'this flower
is red' where the inherence of the red colour in the flowere stands as related
to that flower and that colour, this second relation need not, because there
is no special reason
or immediate evidence, be a separate object. Not that it is therefore a
subjective construction only. We have seen why, according to [Nyaya-Vai'sesika],
it has to be taken as real. It follows that such relations are real and
yet not other than thereals
they relate. Such relation are the [suarupa] of the [Padarthas] related.
The [above] is the account of the object of normal [savikalpa-pratyaksa].
the account of the false object (assuming that falsity has been detected)
is different. In erroneous [savikalpa-pratyaksa] the total object is definitely
known to be not real.Hence
though, like the object of normal [savikalpa-Pratyaksa], is too is broken
up into real elements and a relation, can the relation be taken as teh [svarupa]
of the elements, seeing that the total object is not real? Ordinarily we
should say 'No'.But
[Nyaya-Vai'sesika] prefers to stick to the claim that [vikalpa] relations
are the [svarupa] of the [Padarthas] related. They stick to it, only because
it has followed from the fundamental postulate that whatever appears as independent
is really independent.
Object, everywhere, is to be analysed into the constituent reals and the
[vikalpa] relations, whcih latter are everywhere exhausted in those reals.
But how, then, could the total object be unreal here? [Nyaya-Vai'sesika]
replies as follows: The total object here is no close unity. When the illusion
is exposed the elements cannot be said to have been apprehended as realted
in the way of substantive-adjective identity (samanadhikaranya). The unity
here is loose, it is of the form 'P is inS',
not of the form 'S is P'; and such unity is only nominal, no genuine unity.
This, in effect, means that when the illusion is exposed we cannot say there
was any genuine close unity of S (this) and P (snake). Not that 'P is in
S' is never a close unity. Rather, normally it develops into that. 'P is
in S' is easily translatable into 'P is as in S'='S is with P' which is a
close unity. But such translation is sometimes impossible, particularly
when it is known
for certain that there is no real 'P as in S'. 'Horns are in the hare' cannot
be translated into 'Horns are as in the hare'. While a denial of the former
is intelligible it is impossible to deny the latter in the form 'Hornas as
in hare are not'.Every
judgment, whether affirmative or negative, presupposes that at least the
subject-term stands for a reality, but 'horns as in the hare' stands from
the begining as self-condemned. There is no suchdififculty, on the other
hand, in the judgment 'Horns
in the hare are not'. This judgment is only form 'Horns are not in teh hare',
the corresponding affirmative judgment cannot but be in the form 'Horns are
in the hare', not 'Horns are as in the hare'. Teh false object of an illusion
corrected has also
to be understood
in this form. We cannot say 'This is snake' or 'The snake is as in the locus',
we must say 'The snake is in the locus'. In the case of "hare's horn"
or 'this snake' we are compelled to say this, only because stating the situation
the other
way about would stand self-condemened: we already know taht "hare's
horn" or 'this snake' is not real. Denial of substantive-adjective
identity does not, however, mean that there is no [vikalpa] relation here.
Every [savikalpa-jnana] must involve [vikalpa] relations that are also asserted
as real. But here the [vikalpa] relation is anything but identity.
It is [samsarga], meaning any relation but identity. Teh 'in' in 'horns
in the hare' or 'snake in the locus' is the [vikalpa] relation of [samsarga].
A distinction should be drawn between (a) [ghato nilah] (the pot is black),
(b) [ghate nilah](black
colour is in the pot) and (c) [ghato nilah (the pot is with black colour).
In (a) the [vikalpa] relation is substantive-adjective identity (samanadhikaranya).
In (b) it is [samsarga]. In (c) it is more complicated : there is a turn
back to [samana-dhikaranya]
through [samsarga]. Normally (b) and (c) coincide. But in cases like "hare's
horn" or 'this snake' (b) fails to amount to (c). In the case (b) the
content is peculiar. Though there is the [vikalpa] relation of [samsarga]
the total objectis
not a close unity. A pure case of (b) is not indeed a normal occurrence.
We have to recognise it only where we are already assured that there is
no real total object, as in the case of error. In [Nyaya-vai'sesika], object
(visaya) is neither wholly reducible to knowledge and its phases, and is
so far real, nor wholly equated to reality (padartha), though it is [svarupa]
of that. Object as the real-that- is-known is as much real also. Wereit
the real itself there would have been no occasion to distinguish between
the real and the real-as known. But, again, even as not entirely the real,
it si also exhausted in, i.e., the [svarupa] of the real. Also objectivity,
though not wholly reducible
to knowledge and its phases, is yet constituted by knowledge, being unintelligible
apart from the fact that the corrsponding real is being known. Almost all
Indian thinkers accept this view. Those who accept it differ only in further
details. But most
of the Western thinkers would reject it altogether. Western realists would
never admit the intermediate object: they hold that knowledge is straight
in relation with the real. Idealists and semi-idealists in the West would
also, contrarily, deny object,
reducing it to knowledge and its phases, and either reject the so- called
real thing or admit it as never bodily knowable. A Berkeley would deny the
real altogether, and a Kant or a Hegel would go the second way about. In
defence of the intermediate object Indian thinkers would argue as follows:
Awareness fo a real is either judgmental (savikalpa) or pre-judgmental (nirvikalpa).
When it is [savikalpa] certain relation-forms of judgment-creep in . What
is the status of these forms? Are they modes (or functions) of knowledge,
or are they real,
or both ? On the
first alternative,realism, at least with regard to the content of [savikalpa]
knowledge, is gone. On the third alternative there would indeed be a type
of realism, but is would be more Indian than Western. The second alternative
would
only add difficulties. Are hypothetical and disjunctive forms and forms
of inference real in the realistic sense ? They evidently involve subjective
experiment; and so the contents of hypothetical and disjunctive forms and
forms fo inference, embodythe
experiment: the resulting propositions, and the conclusion are in the form
'if -then-', 'either-or-'and 'therefore-'. Attempts to get rid of such embodiment
of the experiment have always looked forced. The reduction of the hypothetical
propositionto
the categorical may be a piece of skilful translation work, but no hypothetical
proposition ever means a categorical fact only. It follows that the reduction
of the disjunctive proposition to the categorical is equally a faliure, for
such reduction is
possible through another reduction, viz., of the disjunctive to the hypothetical.
It is doubtful, again, if even the latter reduction is complete and natural.
Even if a disjunctive proposition can be analysed into two or four (or whatever
be the number)
hypothetical propositions we must not forget that the disjunctive proposition
is the unity of those hypotheticals, that unity being its specific characteristic.
The attempt to get rid of the "therefore" in inference would
also be equally abortive,that
"therefore" being the very characteristic feature of inference.
There is indeed something like "because- therefore" in the hypothetical
proposition also; but it is only like that. In "because- therefore"
the antecedent stands asserted. But it is
not so asserted in "if-then.", unless "if-then" be only
an apologetic softening of "because - there-fore". What, now,is
true of these judgments and inference is true equally of categorical judgments,
affirmative or negative judgment involves subjective experiment. There is
such experiment so far at least as the possibility (yogyata) fo the negatum
being related
to its locus is concerned. The experiment is also embodied in the content,
though not so obvertly as before. In hypothetical and disjunctive judgments,
and also in inference, the embodiment was evident in the forms of "if-then",
"either -or" and "because-thereofre";
but [Possibility] which is an embodiment of subjective experiment is not
stated explicitly in a negative judgment. Yet if the negatum were not understood
as a possible real relatable to the locus, there would be no negative judgmentat
all. "S is not P' necessarily implies, though this implication does
not come up to the surface, that a possible reality P relatable to S does
not stand so related to it. Though negation, whether by way of identity
or that of [samsarga], may be a reality
the form of the negative judgment-which form is also inevitably asserted
of the content- is not a reality in the realistic sense. As regards affirmative
judgment, one type of it, viz., the universal, cannot have a form that can
pass unchallenged as realistically real. Like negation, the universal judgment
we do not merely assert a universal related to another universal. In the
judgment
"All men are mortal" we inevitably assert all individual men also
(taken in denotation) as related to either mortality or mortal beings. How,
now, are all individual men apprehended here ? We do not apprehend every
man with his particular features,
we apprehend him as only a case of the universal humanity. Individual men
are, in other words, known through our knowledge of that universal. This
need not be the [samanyalaksana-Pratyaksa] of the [Naiyayikas]. We may not
[Perceive] all individual
men, and this is possible if only we apprehend all men through our knowledge
of the universal humanity. A subjective experiment is thus involved, and
the experiment is embodied in the form "all". "All X's"
cannot be a purely realistic fact. The Russellian
idea of such "all". as an open class is unacceptable. In the
judgment "All men are mortal" we do not mean that A,B, C,D, .........and
so on are mortal. There is no sense of privation here. It does not mean
that the men whom you and I have
seen and those whom
we have not seen are mortal. This would be unduly apologetic. What is positively
meant is that all individual men are mortal. We mean, in other words, a
closed class, as much closed and positive as any group of enumerable things,
the only difference
between the two being that while the number in the latter is finite that
in the former is infinite (not negative infinite, but positive). Russell
could at all interpret "all" in his way because he was predisposed
to denying the connotative
universal. His interpretation would have been legitimate were he able to
account forthe total meaning of "all" without having recourse to
the connotative universal. But in the interest of economy he sacrificed
at least an important part of thetotal
meaning. We mean by "all" a positively infinite number of individuals.
Such an "all" is not an absurdity as a Russellian would have us
believe. A closed class of a postively infinite number of individuals is
intelligible if understood through (the
presupposed knowledge of ) the corresponding connotative universal. Whether
or not that connotative universal is itself also meant by "all"
is not the point here. It is enough that at least the positively infinite
number of individuals are meant. Likewise the simple categorical form "this
S is P" cannot also taken as real in the realistic sense. In such judgments
the predicate as almost always universal is to be understood, in the way
of a universal subject, as somehow referring to all individuals,
and therefore through a corresponding universal. Where the predicate is
not a universal, or supposing that a universal need not be understood in
denotation, there is still another reason-and that is more primary-why the
form "this S is P" cannot be
real in the realistic
sense. The relation meant by the copula "is" embodies a subjective
experiment, though only covertly. The relation meant is neither inherence
nor contact nor any taht is a [Padartha] in the [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] sense.
It is one that
relates S, P and that [Padartha] relation into a unittary object, and is,
therefore a [vikalpa]. Thsi [vikalpa] is not consciously felt as experiment.
But it must be one such. We have already proved that every [vikalpa] is
knowledgewise-ness is noother
than the fact that a mode of knowledge is embodied in the content. Over
and above S, P and the [Padartha] relation a second relation which as unifying
the three has to be admitted cannot be real in the realistic sense. C. Some
clarifications- There are two questions which should be answered at this
stage. It may be asked if thsi relation also does not require another relation,
and so on [ad infinitum]. It may also be asked if the original [Padartha]
relation does at all require the seond relation.
To the first question the reply is in the negative. The second relation
was required only to relate into a unity three items of reality one of which
happened to be a relation. Before that unification there were only three
items. But now that they stand
unified through the second relation which is a [vikalpa], there is no task
left to relate thsi second relation again to the three items by further relations.
The reply to teh second question is in the affirmative. The first original
relation was not sufficient to have formed the unity that is meant by the
judgment "This S is P'. Often it is no genuine relation, but only a
quality or even a substantive-indeed,
anything whatever-which is somehow taken as intermediate between S and P.
As such it cannot by itself relate S and P and (itself also) into a unity.
When a so-called relation is a reality of this kind anothere relation whcih
is genuinely a relation
is requisitioned to do that work. But whatever else there is in the world
of reals, thsi genuine relation is not there till that S, P and the so-called
relation stand unified in knowledge. "Unified in knowledge", we
repeat, does not preclude the possibility
that they stand unified in the world of reals also. Teh unsophisticated
mind takes them as also forming a real unity, for such is the plain realistic
import of the judgment. The fact that S,P and their so-called relation are
unified in knowledge and that yet the unity formed is real may be understood
in three ways of which one only is tenable. It may mean taht S,P and the
so-called relation only appear to be really related.
Secondly, it may mean that they had been standing as already really related
before I had the [savikalpa] knowledge, but that this real unity comes to
be revealed only with that [savikalpa] knowledge, alomst in the same way
in which [Vai'sesika] understands
[samanya]. Or, thirdly, it may mean that they were not standing as really
unified, but become related and unified just when I know them in the [savikialpa]
way. Of these, the first alternative is rejected on the plain ground that
no appearance can
be dismissed as mere appearance or false unless there is a reason here for
the dismissal, viz., that the genuine [vikalpa] relation has come to be knownas
a mode of knowledge. For we cannot overlook the other side, viz., that it
is also asserted as real.
To show merely that something is A does not prove that its appearance as
B is unreal. For that another step is necessary. Either we must point to
a clear defect (dosa) in that appearance or at least its being A is to be
a matter of inference, itbeing
presumed for the present that inference is a stronger [Pramana] than perception.
But here the [vikalpa] relation to be a mode of knowledge is not a matter
of inference. It is true the knowledgewise-ness of the [vikalpa] relationis
not always evident
; but for one who has perceived that because-therefore, either-or, if-then,
A as not B and all A are knowledge-wise it is not difficult to perceive that
even the simple categorical form is also a mode of knowledge, particularly
when it is realsied that
S, P and their so-called relation cannot unify themselves. Knowledgewise-ness
of the categorical form does not merely follow from the impossiblity of unification,
it comes also to be immediately realised. There is, again, no specifiable
defect in our
awareness (which is quite primary) that the genuine relation is fact. Hence
the dimissal of it as sheer appearance or false would be unjustified. Even
if the knowledgewise-ness of the categorical [vikalpa] were merely a matter
of inference, there is no reason why inference here should be preferred to
the immediate knowlege that the [vikalpa] is real. Inference is preferred
to immediate knowledge
either when it not
merely contradicts but definitely sublates (why, we may not say) the content
of immediate knowledge, or when it is followed by the perception of a defect
in that immediate knowledge, or when our point of view is that of [Pramanya],
not
of primary assertion which is present as much in inference as in perception.
In the present case the inferred knowledgewise-ness of the [vikalpa] does
nothing of the sort, and the point of view is [ex-hypothesi] not of [Pramanya]
Inference is sometimes regarded as a stronger [Pramana] on the ground that
it is supported by many cognitions that are involved in it. But the point
of view of corroboration is that of [Pramanya], not of primary assertion.
The [Pramanya] of a cognition
may be extrinsic to that cognition as primary assertion, in whcih case it
is doubtful if [Pramanya] has any metaphysical import. Or it may be intrinsic
in which case the entire problem of [Pramanya] is a little more than explication.
Either way the attitude
of [Pramanya] is not very relevant to primary assertion. It would be useless
to argue that when a cognition is confirmed from the point of view of [Pramanya]
chances of its possible rejection are eliminated. Mere elimination of possible
errorsdoes
not make a cognition valied unless it were already so taken, though amidst
a mass of confusions. A Particular cognition can also be dismissed as erroneous
if it is succeeded by one which is its contradictory, the idea being that
a cognition is the assertion of a genuine reality till it comes to be contradicted.
[Uttarajnanapksapata] belongs, in this
sense, to the very constitution of knowledge. But in the present case there
is a strange phenomenon. The knowledge that the [vikalpa] relation is a
mode of knowledge may be later than the assertion of that relation as real,
yet when that later knowledge
occurs the prior one is not sublated. Both continue with unabated primacy.
The reality of this relation, then, cannot be false or sheer appearance.
The second alternative mentioed in page 36 above, ivz., that S,P and their
so-called relation had already formed a unity and is only reveraled in [savikalpajnana],
has also to be rejected. The unity could not have been formed by the so-called
relation, and
a fresh relation whcih alone could form it could not have been there before
the [savikalpajnana], because, as already shown, it is knowledge-wise. It
has also been shown that the simple categorical form, quite as much as other
forms of proposition,
embody subjective
experiment. Hence the third alternative alone is left. The [vikalpa] relation
and the unity occur as real only when S,P and their so-called relation are
known in the [savikalpa] way. This does not mean that the [savikalpajnana]
as an efficient cause has producedsomething
in the reals concerned. Waht is meant is that the propostional form, though
knowledge-wise, comes to be asserted as involved in those reals. Though
knowledge-wise, it comes to be asserted as real also; and as thsi is not
self-contradictory, it
can be taken as really real. But is not a real independent of the knowledge
of it, and does this not imply that it existed before that knowledge occurred
? If something appears real only so long as it is known, is it not for that
very reason called unreal ? The answer depends on what is meant by the word
"reality". If it means 'that which exists and is independent fo
the knowledge of it', the [vikalpa] relation and the unity are real, because
even though they are constituted by knowledge they are yet asserted
as existent and independent of knowledge, and we have seen how to be constituted
by knowledge does not clash with this other character. It follows that to
have remained prior to knowledge is not necessary for something to be real.
Many reals may be
so prior, but some need not be. Or, it may be said that the [vikalpa] and
the unity had remained prior to knowledge, but as so prior they were not
actually existent. They come to exist only when they are known. As subsistent,
[vikalpa] relations remain in their self-contained aloofness,
and relate, S,P and their so-called relation only when these latter come
to be known, and through that knowledge. It is because they yet maintain
their Platonic ideality that they refuse to be wholly identified with that
knowledge and procalim themselves
as prior to that knowledge; and it is because they now stand as relating,
and therefore adjectival to, the actually real S,P and their so-called relation
that they in that function come to be known as actually existent. This is
more or less the Kantian
view of [vikalpas]. whichever interpretation is accepted we have to admit
grades of metaphysical status. In the first interpretation there would be
two kinds of reality, one co-temporal with knowledge and the other transcending
its duration; and
as this distinction
concerns the very existence, not the content, it is a distinction of metaphysical
status. The distinction between subsistence (demand for existence) and
actual existence is obviously a distinction of metaphysical status. The
Indian position has been vindicated. It has been shown that over and above
reality, though not necessarily separate from it, object has to be admitted.
This has been established through an analysis of the metaphysical import
of though-forms. Theonly
conceivable way to get rid of this intermediate entity would be to deny that
forms of thought have any metaphysical import. Logical Positivists have
attempted this in their systematic campaign aganist thought. They consider
forms of thought as either
only means to analytical interpretation, the whole interpretation being only
linguistic, or vicarious, misrepresenting a clever language-construction
as pointing to a reality. But it is difficult to see why thought should
be so unceremoniously guillotined. Mass hysteria is no logical justification.
These Positivists ought to have seen that no judgment, not even the simple
categorical, is either a mere analytical representation
of a non-judgmental content-what to speak of non-perceptual judgments which
are obviously not so ? - or, because of the extral element involved in it,
vicarious, for we all believe that the total content of the judgment is real
exactly in the form in
which it appears
in the judgment. We have already seen that in spite of being knowledge-wise
the extra element is nevertheless felt as real and taht the two aspects do
not clash. These Positivists have never explained why among the devils of
judgmentsome,
viz., a good number of perceptual judgments, are obedient slaves. We can
understand Kant who has excluded a very limited number of judgments, and
that on definite grounds. But these Positivists have stated with a bias.
They have indeed shown extra-ordinary
skill in translating non-perceptual judgments into the language of simple
perception. But translation always falls short of the original: the original
vitality is always missed and there is only vicarious compensation. Perceptual
judgments do not merely analytically represent contents of simple perception.
In simple perception there is a bare plurality of S,P and a so-called relation
between them, all appearing either discrete or non-distinguished. But the
judgment"This
S is P" means that S and P, and sometimes their so-called relation also,
are distinguished and yet related into a unity. We have said that in simple
perception S, P and their so-called relation are [either ] discrete or non-distinguished.
The former is the [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] view according to which simplw perception
(nirvikalpa-Pratyaksa) is certified not by introspection
but by inference, and the simple elements that are inferred as constituting
a substantive-adjective complex perceived have to be inferred as discrete.
But one is not compelled to accept the [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] view that simple
perception has only to be
inferred. One might
hold that it is an introspectable stage. In this other view the simple constituents
are not found as discrete, but in a sense non-distinguished. Let us explain,
how. If there is any Psychological stage, called non-judgmental perception,
it is of the form SP (this blue pot-nilaghatah) which differs from "this
S is P" in that while in the latter S and P are both distinguished
and related, the relation standing as a distinct
entity, we do not find thsi phenomenon in the simple SP. Not that SP is
therefore and amorphous homogeneity, as Bradley would have it. If there
is at all a Psychological stage having the simple content SP, we are aware,
at that very stage, of S
and P also, the
three contents-S, P and SP- alternating indeterminately, each, at the time
it is apprehended, standing as absolute. When we are aware of S there is
no question of either P or SP, and similarly with P, but as much an absolute
entity astaht
S or P. A whole, in simple perception, is never known as a whole of parts.
For that apprehension the parts and the whole require to be related in a
judgmental form of awareness. The very words "parts' and "whole"
are relevant in a judgment context
only. If A, B and C are three absolute entities, C is a whole, and A and
B are parts, only when between C, on the one hand, and A and B, on the other,
a certaing relation of dependence is asserted, when, eg., it is known that
while A and B are dissociable
from C, C is not so dissociable from A and B; and such knowledge cannot be
simple perception. Similarly with regard to any other unity. A universal
or a substance, e.g., is felt as dissociable from the relevant particulars
or attributes, but not the
latter from the former. In simple perception, then, S,P and SP are each
absolute, and there is no question of a relation between them. But in the
judgment "This S is P"S and P (and it may be, their so-called relation
also) are related in a specifiable
way in the unity SP. The indeterminate alternation of several absolutes
is thus, in simple categorical judgment, replaced by determinate relation.
In simple perception S,P and SP are each absilute. SP is not a unity, but
as much an absolute entity as S or P. It may indeed be asked-Do not S and
P stand involved in SP ? How otherwise could it be known as SP ? The reply
is that in simple perception
it is not known as SP, but merely as an absolute entity with a differential
quality perceived. It is only retrospectively called SP, called that way
from the point of view of the latter judgment "S is P." But, it
may be asked again, is not that SP known,
at least in this retrospective manner, as identical with the unity known
in the judgment "S is P" ? We reply -Yes, there is only as much
unity as between object and reality. We thus find that even simple perception
is not so simple as Logical Positivists believe. It too involves an extra
element, the as yet undefined differential quality. The logical form of
the simple categorical judgment may be understood as linguisticdefinition
of this quality. But it is not like definitions elsewhere. In other cases
of definitions there is no line, except in the verbal presentation, between
the definitum and the definition. Here there is such a line. Yet, however,
the linguistic form
is asserted as real without any sense of inconsistency. We have also seen
that there is no contradiction in a though (language)-construction here being
real. It may be asked-if in the world of reals there are inherence (samavaya),
contact (samyoga), etc., are they not genuine relations relating S and P
into a unity, even apart from my knowing them ? The answer should be prefaced
by a more fundamental problem to be raised here and solved. If at a non-judgmental
stage we can at all apprehend S, P and SP which are real, is there at that
stage any object over and above those reals ? The problem, in other
words, is if even in non-judgmental perception ther is the intermediate entity
called object ? We reply- There is. If the reals here are S, P and SP,
the object is these in indeterminate alternation. In [savikalpajnana] there
are definite [vikalpa] relations binding relas into unities, but here in
the place of thsoe definite [vikalpas] there is
only indeterminate
alternation, and therefore also an inddeterminate unity through that alternation.
The unit that is effected by alternation is always indeterminate, as is
evident in the case of disjunctive judgment. Here, however, in the present
case,
the alternation it self is indeterminate, and hence the unity effected is
unlike one in disjunctive judgment. The unity here is not judgmental: the
stage in question is below even simple categorical judgment. But there is
still a unity, though at the
vanishing point; and the vanishing unity is here the object. The object
here is more coincident with reals than in [savikalpajnana]. The object
and the real here are not [definitely] distinguishable. It may stall be
asked if even at this stage the real SP is not apprehended as different from
S and P, and, if so, whether the distinction can be anything but that thsi
SP is a unity of S and P. The unity may be inderminate, but is it not a
unity still? If
so, has not the unity been effected by some elements in the region of reals,
viz., inherence, contact, etc., is possible, why was it said before that
these are only so-called relation, not relation that unify and, therefore,
relate reals ? With this
we come to the question asked at the beginning of thsi sub-section. The
answer is that indeterminate unity is qualitatively different from one that
is determinate. Indeterminate unity of S and P is little more than their
alternation, as we find even in disjunction. When, again, the alternation
itself is indeterminate,
even SP which is
the indeterminate unity of S and P alternates with that S and P. This latter
means that though the difference between SP, on the one hand, and S and P,
on the other, is now a little more defined the situation still remains indefinite.
Indeterminate unity
at the non-judgmental level, then, means either that S and P are only alternating
with onw another or that SP comes to stand with just a differential quality,
not further defined. Even where S and P merely alternate they stand eachwith
a differential quality, and the quality is such that though it distinguishes
S-with -that -emergent-quality from simple S, and P -with-that-emergent-quality
from simple P, it is apprehended as somehow also the same in both. This
vague sameness or identity
of the differential quality, as appearing to transcend, on account of thsi
identity, S and P comes to be represented as some sort of unity in the vague
form of SP even here. The unities effected by inherence and contact, and
the latter as relations, are to be understood in this light. When S and
P in contact effect SP what is apprehended at the non-judgmental level is
(i) that S and P have each a differential quality which
is, only retrospectively
from the point of view of a later [savikalpajnana], represented as S-in-cantact-with-P
or P-inpcantact-with-S, and (ii) that somehow the contact is also felt as
numerically one and the same, so that we also say tha S and P are in
contact, the result being SP. The self-identical contact as standing between
S and is never apprehended as an explicit definite real, what is expplicitly
felt being only the indeterminate alternation of S-with-that-differentail-qualty
and P-with-that-differential-quality.
That this indeterminate alternation is at all felt, however vaguely, as
the self-identical contact between S and P is no more than an incipient interpretation
of the alternation in terms of [savikalpajnana](judgment). Judgment is
so much a normal mode of knowing that even when we are aware that there
is a non-judgmental mode, we, in spite of all caustion, involuntarily smuggle
its form, though now in disguise, into the non-judgmental content. Contact
is really a differential
quality of each
term, the contact of P with S being different from and alternating with the
contact of S with P. Indian thinkers have always taken contact as qualities
of S and P alternating. Contact includes a host of relations. Parts of
a whole, e.g., are in contact with one another: the spatial relation of the
parts with one another is, in other words, nothing but a form of contact.
The spatial relation of up-down, right-left, etc., are
in many cases forms
of contact, with, of course, additional differential qualities at the level
of non-judgmetal perception. The additional differentail quality is only
retrospectively definable in terms of dik. Often, again, this differential
quality
alone is found, when, e.g., S and P are not in contact. As with spatial
relation, so with corresponding temporal relations. Often, again, the contact
is with the very principles of space and time. Into further niceties we
need not enter. A host of other relations are represented by inherence.
The relation, e.g., between a whole and a part, a universal and a particular,
a quality and a substance, is inherence. But at the non-judgmental level
it is not apprehended as a definite relation
relating S and P.
At that level it is only a differential quality of SP. SP no doubt alternates
with S and P, but stands evident with that differential quality. The differential
quality is only retrospectively specificable as teh fact that from the total
situation SP either S or P is dissociable and the other not. at the non-judgmental
level there is only a vague sense of thsi dissociability. A whole or a universal
or a substance is only vaguely felt as dissociable from the total situation,
and the
parts, particulars or qualties are vaguely felt as dissociable from the total
situation, and the parts, particulars or qualities are vaguely felt as undissociable.
The total situation SP is felt with this differential quality. Some Western
thinkers and the Buddhists have missed the differntial quality corresponding
to what is called inherence and have accordingly denied the reality of the
whole, the universal and the substance. Some of them have committed a further
mistake of
missing the reality-aspect of [vikalpa] relations, and thsi has led them
to deny all reality to relation and unities. But, as is evident now, both
these are exaggeration. The Buddhist position will be examined later. F.
Object-reality distinction evident in correction of illusion The distinction
between objec and the real will also be evident from an analysis of illusion
as corrected. Before correction the content of illusion is felt as real
object. But after correction it stands as an object minus the reality-aspect,
so thatto
the end it is still an object, though of a peculiar type, unconnected, or
better, disconnected, with reality. This disconnection is not a normal feature
of objects. But the illusory content is an abornal object, and because illusion
is cancelled weare
forced to admit such disconnection. Some believe that the corrected content
as over and above reality is no object but subjective. [Vijnanavadi Buddhists]
India and many thinkers in the West have held this view. The [Vijnanavadin's]
view will be examined later. They have offered arguments,
and these will be examined in due course. But the Western thinkers who have
passed this as almost self-evident have only confused different issues.
That appearance is distinct from reality is one issue, and whether what is
distinct from reality is
no sufficient reason
that it is subjective. Further, these Western thinkers have misunderstood
object as wholly identified with the real, and have naturally been driven
to the conclusion that what is not real is, on that very account, not object,
and is
therefore subjective. But we have seen that object is neither unqualified
real nor unqualifiedly subjective (knowledge-wise). There is another point
to be considered in connection with the thesis that in correction of illusion
we realise object as over and above reality. The object here is not necessarily
the content of [savikalpa-pratyaksa]. It includes the content of [nirvikalpa-pratyaksa]
as well, supposing there is such a stage evident to judgmental or non-judgmental-object,
in spite of being knowledge-wise, is found coincident with the real, it is
apprehended as loosened when a perception comes to be corrected. We have
seen that in non-perceptual knowledge [vikalpas] and, therefore, objects
are clearly felt as knowledge-wise (experimental), though not for that reason
denied reality. But this knowledgewise-ness, we have also seen, is not so
manifest in [savikalpa-perception],
far less in [nirvikalpa]; object in these two cases is not clearly felt as
distinct from the real. Our present thesis is that the distinction of the
perceptual object-a determinate unity or an indeterminate whole-from the
real stands exposed in
correction. By implication it is admitted that even non-judgmental simple
perception (nirvikalpa-Pratyaksa) can be erroneous. We are often told, particularly
by Western thinkers, that is non-judgmental simple perception there is no
question of falsity, all question of truth or falsity arising only when knowledge
is judgmental (savikalpa). This is untenable. If the content of
non-judmental perception
be S,P and SP alternating, with a differential quality of either S and P
or SP, there is no reason why this content should not be as much true or
false as the content of judgment: all the difference between the two kinds
of knowledge
is that while in the latter there is explicit relation there is only a differential
quality (or qualities) in the former. There is a kind of vague predication
(unification), in the form of differential quality, in non-judgmental perception
only.May
not a simple content, not known as related with another be true or false
? When it is apprehended is it not asserted as real, and may not such assertion
come in certain cases to be sublated later? The whole question as to whether
the content of non-judgmental perception can or cannot be true or false depends
on what is meant by the word "truth" or "falsity". If
"truth" means that the content of knowledge exists, there is truth-claim
in non-judgmental
perception, for it too is asserted, i.e., taken as existent. Similarly if
"falsity" means that the once-asserted existence of the content
is now disbelieved - disbelief being not necessarily judgmental, but at lest
in some cases the awareness ofa
differential quality of the content- there is nothing against a non-judgmental
congnition being false. An analysis of the very concept of judgmental rejection
would corroborate this. Judgmental rejection=rejective judgment may be perceptive
or non-perceptive-in Indian terminology, [savikalpa-pratyaksa] and [savikalpa-Paroksajnana].
Where it is perceptive
there is in the content perceived a differential qulity corresponding to
the [vikalpa] relation of contradiction, over and above that contradiction
itself. It is only when the rejective judgment is non-perceptive (Paroksa)
that there is no question of
that diffeential quality, and rejection in such cases is either through
a categorical or hypothetical inference or through a categorical or hypothetical
inference or through testimony. Thus even perceptual rejective judgment
is intelligible through a
perceived differential
quality, corresponding to the relation of contradiction, in the content rejected
(though there is in the content the explicit relation of contradiction also).
If so, the differential quality is, at lest in some cases, a sufficient
ground for the rejection of the content. Why, then, may not the content
of non-judgmental cognition be also rejected, when in it too a similar differntial
quality comes to be perceived ? Truth, however, and therefore falsity also,
may mean something else. Truth may mean that the existence of the content
is explicitly asserted, as in the judgment 'SP exists', and such assertion
is always the confirmation of a prior knowledge of the content.
Truth, in this sense, is but the confirmedness of that prior cognition,
so that the esixtence of the content has come to be specifically pointed
to. Falsity would, from this point of view, be the [untenability[ of the
prior cognition and, therefore,
the explicit rejection of the content. Thsi is the problem of [Pramanya]
in Indian philosophy, not always clearly distinguished in the West from the
simple assertion of the existence or non-existence of a content/ If truth
and falsity are understood from this reflective point of view it would be
admissible indeed that only judgments can be true or false. But there should
be a note of caution at the same time that this is not true of all judgments,
so that judgmentality
is one [sine qua non] of truth and falsity. Existential judgments and judgments
of modality alone can be true or flase-judgments, namely, where existence
or its near equivalent is stated as the explicit predicate. In other judgments
there is no
such explicit statement. In the judgment 'S is P,' for example, the copula
'is' represents more an explicit [vikalpa] relation than explicit existence
of the content SP. That it appears to stand equally for both is an accident
of English language.
In Sanskrit we
find that 'ghato nilah' is a sufficient expression, and the statement 'ghato
nilo bhavati' is not required. There is logical ground also. Even in English
language the existential import can be explicitly distinguished, as in the
judgment
'SP exists'; and it is plain logic that if somethind can be distinguished
it, where not distinguished, remains implicit and subordinate. The copula
in 'S is P' thus only implicitly and subordinately conveys the existence
of SP. Obvertly it represents
a relation only between S and P. If it be insisted that after all the existential
import is still present, though not explicitly, in the judgement 'S is P,'
we reply that it is equally present in non-judgmental perception also. As
much in the latter as in the former the total contentis
known as existent. It has sometimes been urged that even judgments like
'S is P,' as distinguished from the non-judgmental awareness or SP, is against
a doubt or challenge that S might not be P, so that as so against the doubt
or the challenge it ismore
reflective than the non-judgmental awareness of SP and, therefore, assertss
so far the existence of the content explicitly. But this would be a wrong
understanding of the actual situation. 'S is P' is certainly more reflective
than SP, and perhaps
non-judgmetal awareness
is not reflective at all. But the reflectiveness of the former does not
lie in its being against a doubt or challenge. Here there is neither an
actual nor a possible doubt (or challenge). That there is no actual doubt
can hardly can hardly be questioned. There is no possible doubt too; for
a possible one is no more than that which I in judging that way only anticipate,
and it is a fact that I did not anticipate one. Had I anticipated,the
judgment would have been of the form 'S is P,' with an emphasis on the existential.
The simple judgments would be hardly distingusihable from the existential.
The simple judgment 'S is P' is reflective in the sense that it is against
the background of
a half-distinguished assumption of the abstract content 'S as P.' This 'S
as P' as half -distinguished is no other than the unity-through-vikalpa-relation
considered apart from its reality aspect. Sometimes, again, a thrid reason
is offered why only judgment, and not non-judgmental awareness, can be true
or false. It is said that as only judgment involves a sort of spontaneity,
either because [vikalpa] relations are considered as acts or because
a constructed general
idea is papended to the subject, the question of the truth of the judgmentsal
knowledge naturally crops up. But this, again, is both a too simple and
a uselessly complicated account. To simple, because whether vikalpas be
acts or not,
and whether a general idea be a construction or not, there is also the undeniable
fact that every judgment asserts the reality of the total content. To foreget
this aspect and to insist on the vikalpa relations being subjective would
be over-simplification.
There is also unnecessary complication in that the vikalpas are taken as
acts or, even by some, as forms of will, and general ideas are taken as mere
constructions, whereas the peculiar character of judgment is intelligible
even in the absence
of any such theory. So there is no reason why judgments alone should be
true or false, and non-judgmental knowledge outside this disinction. Both
equally are true or false, if 'truth' means that the content is known as
existent, and 'falsity' that it is rejected. Only when
truth is understood as the confimedness of a cognition as against an actual
or a possible challenge, and falsity as the corresponding rejection, can
ordinary of truth and falsity. But as here we are not using the words 'truth'
and 'falsity' in that sense
we hold that all cognition can be true or false. With this we come back
to the problem of the exact status of the illusory content, whether in judgment
or in non-judgmental knowledge. G. Buddhist theory of [atmakhyati] examined
Before an illusion is corrected the total content is taken as a real object.
But after correction it is known as definitely not real and, therefore,
to have been an object minus the reality-aspect. This is what is meant by
rejection of the illusory content.
It would be too much to claim, as some Buddhists have done, that even its
objectivity is rejected. I fthey intend that both objectivity and reality
are denied this would be unnecessary duplication. Rejection of any one of
the two aspects is enough;
so the other aspect has to be retained. It is enough for correction that
the reality-aspect is rejected; hence objectivity ought to be retained.
But why may it not be interpreted the other way about? May it not be said
that the aspect of objectivity
is rejected and the reality-aspect retained ? The Buddhists under consideration
have, as a maater of fact, offered this interpretation. But this would only
make the confusion worse confounded. If the content is real and yet not
an object, it would
be real as only a mdoe of knowledge. But does the corrective judgment assert
this subjective reality ? Do we find that the illusory snake was not an
object but an existent subjective idea ? Correction is either judgmental
or non-judgmental. When judgmental, it is of the form 'this is not snake'
coupled in a mysterious manner with another form, viz., 'this is rope'.
The content 'this as not snake' is a unity, effected through a vikalpa relation,
of a real this and either a real snake (when the vikalpa relation is negative)
or the absence of snake. The content 'this as rope' is also a real unity
of a real this and a real rope. In either case there is no escape from the
this-element which
is no subjective idea. The Buddhists in question have held that the content
of correction is 'not this, but snake'. But even if thsi be allowed there
is the other content 'this is rope' inseparably connected with it. In that
other content this-element is asserted as existent,
and it is also evident that this [this] is somehow non-different from the
[this] in 'not this, but snake'. It is impossible that in the same correction
the same [this] is both asserted as existent and rejected. That in the content
'this is rope' it
is asserted as existent
is beyond question. It follows that 'not this, but snake' is a mis-representation
of the other content. That other content is either 'this, not snake' or
'this and snake, but no predicational identity of the two' or 'this and snake,
but the two not consciously distinguished', etc., all of which are representable
as 'this is not snake'. The Buddhist theory of [atmakhyati] cannot pass
unchallenged. Even if we allow the form ' not this, but snake', it does
not follow that the snake-aspect is subjective. That would presuppose that
'this' means to be now outside me. But 'this' does not mean that. Even
an idea which no one can call outside is a this
to me if it is now. The concept 'this' is highly intriguing and involves
either now or here which are equally intriguing. To interpret it as ' to
be now outside me' would only be too facile. The [Vijnanavadin] may argue
that snake would still be subjective even if the content of correction were
'this, not snake'. 'Not snake' means that the snake is rejected, and the
rejected snake as ousted, on the one hand, from the world of reals and asyet
not zero, on the other hand, cannot but be subjective. But this too would
be a hasty conclusion. In spite of being false, the snake appeared as object.
A theory error which can retain thsi objectivity is to be prefferred to
one which denies it too
easily; and considering what has been sa8id so far about the distinction
of object from reality, the presumption is against the idealsitic theory
of the Buddhists. Correction may also be non-judgmental. But even there,
as in all non-judgemental knowledge, the content is a presented rope with
the peculiar flavour of denied presented snake, or an absent snake with the
preculiar flavour of its being ousted by a now-presented
rope, the once-presentedness of the snake being, of course, no more than
a fringe round the flavour of being ousted. Which-ever way the content appears,
there is no scope for the particular Buddhist theory. In every case the
content is presented
as an object. The rejected snake can in no way be taken as subjectively
real. Indeed the phrase 'subjectively real' is often a camouflage. In what
sense is a subjective idea real ? Is it real in the sense of being independent
of its knowledge, or is it real in the
sense of being just
existent ? The Buddhists under consideration hold that in correction the
outsideness only of the content is denied, and its reality is retained.
But is the subjective reality of the snake its original pre-correction reality
? The pre-correction reality of the sanke
included its having been independent of the knowledge of it, whatever else
it might have included. But at lest that independence is now denied by these
Buddhists. The subjectve snake is than real in some other sense. The reality
of subjectivity is qualitatively different from that of a non-subjective
content. While the reality of a non-subjective content is distinguishable
from that content this is not the case, at lest according to the Buddhists
in question, with
the subjective.
The subjective, at least according to them, is self-evident: to be subjective
is [ipse-facto] to be real. In 'this flower exists' existence can be imagined
as dissociable, as at least a universal belonging to thsi flower, or even
as what
may lapse. But in 'Iam' am-ness is the same thing as I-ness. I=I am. Contrariwise,
the content fo the non-subjective is imaginable apart from existence (or
non-existence), but not so the content of the subjective. If the subjective
can at all be imagined
apart from existence, there is no conceivable way of adding that existence
ever to the content. The subjective is either ever a more content or ever
with existence. Whichever way it is understood, it is evident that the reality
of the subjective,
if at all it is real, is qualitatively different from that of the non-subjective.
To say, therefore, that the snake is subjectively different from that of
the non-subjective. To say,therefore, that the snake is subjectively real
is little more than
saying that it is
just subjecitve. The reality with which we contrast the false is the reality
of the non-subjective. And yet these Buddhists persuade themselves that
in correction the reality of the snake has been retained, as though it is
the same reality
which we had before correction. It is true that there is a natural tendency
to take what is not real (in the realistic sense) as merely my imagination
and, so far, subjective. But there is no assurance till now that the image,
though subjective, does not stand outside. The false snake,
detected as false, may have been a subjective image. But I saw it outside,
and it is not yet certain whether this outsideness came to be cancelled.
It might well be that its reality (existence) alone is cancolled, the snake
being understood as a ghoslty
outside entity, a floating adjective, as it were, of the rope that is real.
An image to stand outside is not Prima facie absurd. In every normal perception
where the content is presentative-representative the representative element,
though imaginal,
stands outside, tied to what is merely presented. If thsi be allowed, why
may not an image, in illuion, stand outside, though unconnected or misconnected
with what is presented ? That which in normal perception made the image
an outside content is
not the correctness
of the perception, but only there being to that perception a presented content.
Inilluion too there is a presented content is not, it is true, eveident
in its full character. But there is no denying the fact that there is a
presented
content. The represented content, again, is not a real adjective of the
presented element. Nevertheless it is an adjective, though false, false
in the sense fo being really unconnected or misconnected. Alike in normal
perception and illusion the image-element
is outside. Imagination may be directed to a past thingor a given presentation,
or to no thing whatever. When directed to a past thing, the insideness
of the image is more evident than its outsideness. The thing no doubt is
remembered,but
as imagination has added nothing to the thing-as-it-was-perceived no special
outsideness of the image is evident. What is evident ofn the other hand
is that to a given presentation, however, the outsideness alone of the image
is evident: the imagestands
tied, it is said, to the presentation. The insideness of the image have
amtured at all into a subjective image. The same thing occurs in illusion;
only, here the image is not directed to anything-past or present-it is ever
on the vanishing point
and is kept steady,even
as so vanishing, by words. In this case-we may call it idea, as distict
from the two previous types of image-it stands evident as merely inside.
The outsideness of the image is complete in the second case only. The complete
outsideness
in the second case and the much less outsideness in the first are equally
due to the reference of the imagination to real things outside. The Buddhists
under consideration have been deluded by the theoretical insideness of the
image. They have
not seen that except in the third case above there is also its outsideness,
evident in its fulness as much in perception as presentative-representative
as in illusion. The idealistic account of the false content is thus untenable.
The false content has to be taken as non-subjective, i.e., an object, though
it may not be a real object. All other Indian theories of error and the
modern realistic theories of Alexanderand
other realists agree in this point. In spite of this general agreement,
however, they differ in some fundamentals, each having understood the concepts
of object, reality and their realtion in a different way. These theories
should be examined separately. H. Some modern realistic theories of error
examined Some modern realists believe that an object as such is neither
real nor unreal and that the reality of a normal object and the unreality
of aone called illusory are equally unmetaphysical, being only contingent
derivative characters. But this is over-simplication in various ways. Let
us see, how. (1) An object that is rejected may be provisionally granted
as subsisting on its own account and having unreality as a contingent derivative
character. But the object of a normal cognition is never felt as subsiting
aloof from reality. If is felt from
the beginning to
the end as absolutely coincident with the real-in other words, as unqualifiedly
real. It is only where there is no assertion, where a content is merely
entertained that one may say it subsists. But such content is in the face
of it an abstraction,
and actually felt that way. EVen doubt, question and suggestion are more
or less assertive. In doubt and question there is still assertion, though
it is either midway between or alternation of affirmation and denial, or
the assertion here
is vague and incomplete.
It cannot be said that in doubt and question there is neither affirmation
nor denial. Suggestion also is not without all assertion. Suggestion is
the mere entertainment of a content-as-asserted. In all other types of cognition,
except in error corrected, there is unambiguous affirmation or denial, though
in the affirmation of one content there may remian involved (and subordinated)
the denial of another content, and vice versa. In such cases the content
is not felt the same
content can be asserted, suggested, questioned, doubted, merely entertained
or even rejected is enough to make one feel that it is at least dissociable,
if not dissociate, from relaity. The content that is simply entertained
is abstract and symbolic,but
a content asserted is felt neither as that abstract one plus its assertedness
nor as symbolic plus something else. No concrete can be broken up adequately
into (several abstract features or)an abstract feature and a dark solod base.
A cow is not analysable
into cowhood and an indenifite solid base; that base is itself also a particular
cow. Had not the base had a definite [svarupa] the universal cowhood could
not be connected with it to the preference of any other particular, say,
one to which doghood
or horsehood belongs. The content asserted is, againg, real, and no reality
is constituted by a bare symbolic possibility and something else. Possiblity
may at the most be the essence of the reall and a corresponding possible
there is nothing that
is explicity common. If Y be a modification of X, it is X in another form,
not X and another form, far less, therefore X and a dark ground. The relation
of an asserted content C to a C that is merely entertained is true [mutadis
mutandis] of its realtion
to C's that are doubted, questioned and suggested. To all these attitudes
there is necver the self-same content except in name, and even that name
C is not the content of simple entertainment. Only the content of correction
is absolutely the same
as what was asserted.
But of that later. The realists under consideration might still argue that
as we ourselves have shown through all these pages that object is different
from the real we ought not to take exception to their view. Should not object
as distinct from the real be taken as neither
existent nor non-existent ? We reply, we hold also that object is yet felt
as coincident with the real, i.e., as itself the real. We have also shown
that there is no reasong why one of these two apprehensions is to be preferred
and the other rejected. To have preferred their distinction
to the extent of rejecting their identity has been the over-simplification
No.I of which these realsits are guilty. There are other acts of over-simplification
also. (2) They have understood the illusory content too hastily. True,
when error is corrected we come to doubt if the content was definitely either
existent or non-existent. But this 'not definitely either existent or non-existent'
does not amount to 'neither
existent nor non-existent'. There is no evidence yet, nor even a reasonable
suggestion, that it was definitely neither. The only case where there is
definite absence of either is simple entertainment where the content is admittedly
abstract; but the content of error even after correction,
does not appear to be abstract. No one feels that the contents of error
should be taken as having been merely supposed or simply entertained. It
need not be denied that the content is not felt as definitely either existent
or non-existent, but
that does not mean that it is definitely neither. It is still asserted,
though neither as existent nor as non-existent. The content corrected is
still asserted in the sense that it is known as a sort of appearance of the
real that is discovered in correction. After correction it is not felt as
floating in the air. It is felt even then as somehow tagged to the real,
not a
self-subsistent content having nothing to do with the real. The question
of unreality of that content at all arises only becausee ther e is such tagging:
this appearance of the real is not a real appearance. (3) These modern realists
are guily or yet another over-simplification. By treating object as such
as neither real nor unreal and interpreting reality and unreality as equally
pragmatic or linguistic or anything else they have missed a notable featureof
the unreal object. In whatever is that which was once apprehended as real.
If it were not understood as 'once apprehended as real, but now rejected,'
even abstract contents (including even the neutral contents of these realists)
would have to be called
unreal. The central problem of erro ris how content can be both objective
and unreal. If the denial of objectivity, as by the [Vijnanavadi Buddhist],
has been too easy, so has been the attempt to treat reality and unreality
as only extrinsic to the content. I. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] theory of error
The illusory content as both object and unreal could not be a problem at
all if object in normal perception were not wholly coincident with the real.
Object to be so coincident with the real is not merely what just happens
when a perception is not erroneous.
It follows, we have seen, from a fundametal postulate of knowledge, at least
of perception. The problem, then, is this :-How can the same object be real
and unreal at teh same time ? The problem can be formulated in another way.
In course of examining the modern realstic theory of error we have shown
that the content rejected is, even after correction, asserted, though neither
definitely as existent nor definitely as real. How can
the rejected content
be yet an appearance of the real ? A can be taken as an appearance of B
if between them there runs a bond of identity. But how can there be a bond
of identityu between the false and the real when the false is definitely
rejected as
unreal ? [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] solves the problem characteristically in close
touch with objective common sense. It holds that though prior to correction
there was the awareness of a total object 'this snake' or 'this is snake,'
correction of it entails that this
awareness was wrong,
another name of which is that the total content is unreal. Yet, however,
the awarencess of it was [savikalpa-Pratyaksa], which implies that some reals
(apprehended in nirvikalpa-Pratyaksa) were related into a unity by [vikalpas]
which
are knowledge-wise. The reals in the present case were this and snake, for
nothing else could be related into the unity 'this is snake.' The this here
was but the real rope perceived as mere this. Its [rope-svarupa] was not
perceived, in other words,
just a given substratum, no [svarupa] of it. The other real was snake, but
not this snake or that snake. Not this snake, because there was no snake
presented. Nor, again, that snake, i.e., a snake, of the past remembered
in relative fullness as the
snake there and then, for that snake could not be combined with a this substratum.
What could be so combined is just snake (sarpamatra). Some past snake is
no doubt remembered, for otherwise there could not be a question of snake
at all; but it is not
remebered as that snake. Only the [snake- svarupa] is remebered. As any
past snake is real, so is also the [snake-svarupa (sarpamatra)] which is
only a part of it. This [snake- svarupa] came to be combined with a this
into the [savikalpa] unity 'this
is snake' through a peculiar psychological mechanism, viz., that the very
memory of the [snake-svarupa] acted as the contact between the sense and
the real substratum. This psychological mechanism does not concern us for
the present. Teh elements thsi and snake are real. The [vikalpa] relation
that combined them into a unity is also real; this follows from the fundamental
postualte of knowledge already mentioned. But unlike the elements and the
vikalpa relation, the unity formed is
not real. In correction this unity stands rejected. This last is the intriguing
feature of illusion. Normally when the elements and the vikalpa relation
are real teh unity effected stands also as real. The present case is an
exception, only because
the unity has been
rejected in correction. Not that I was not aware of the unity before correction,
nor that as an object then it was not apprehended as real. But correction
contradicts just this prior awareness and therefore sublates this object.
It
follows that once it is sublated it cannot be taken to have been real even
before. But if it cannot be said to have been real, how we say that it was
yet an object ? Does not the reality of every object follow from the very
fundamental postualte of knowledge ? The [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] reply is that
it cannot be said to have been an object
even. It was indeed felt as an object, but as a matter of fact it was not
an object. Not that it was therefore wholly subjective. This idealsitic
theory has been already refuted. Moreever, if the elements are real outside
their unity cannot bemerely
subjective. It cannot be said, again, that though the elements are real
by themselves they yet as in the unity must partake of the nature of that
unity. Here there is no question of the elements in the unity: in the unity
there are no elements,there
is only the unity, and nothing else, the elements being only inferred as
having been apprehended in a prior [nirvikalpa] knowledge. The unity in
question is neither merely subjective nor an object coincident with the real.
Not that as neither subjective nor such object it is the neutral object
of the modern reasists. Such neutral objects we have already dismissed.
[Nyaya-Vai'sesika]
is forced to conclude that after correction there is no talk of such unitary
object. Though prior to correction some such unity appeared, correction
is just its sublation. What is meant is this: After correction we cannot
say 'This snake is (was) not'. Such negative judgment is impossible. EVery
judgment, affirmative or negative, is possible if at least the subject is
already known as real. 'A table is not in the room' presupposes that there
is a table in the world (though not in the room). But before we are entitled
to say 'This snake is not' we are already assured that this snake has been
sublated. So there is no occasion to use 'this snake' as the subject of
a judgment. It will be no
use arguing that
though the present this snake is sublated there were other this-snakes at
other times. 'This refers primarily to one unique particular, one that is
presented just here and now, and in comparison with it the use of the word
'this' as characterising
other things which were so presented is abstract and symbolic, not a genuine
living use. Whatever else may be called this, the primary and living use
of the word is regarding a very unique particular entity. This snake is
the very particular
unique snake that was here taken as a real object and is now sublated in
correction. 'This snake', so understood, cannot be the subject of a judgment,
affirmative or negative. The negation of thsi snake, so understood, would
be a case of [aprasaktapratisedha].
If this snake cannot be denied now, it cannot also be taken, from the point
of view of correction, as what was affirmed before correction. From the
point of view of correction, then, this snake was not an object. But do
we not yet, even from the point of view of correction, say 'This snake was
not' or 'This snake was apprehended as object', and do we not mean something
by that ? [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] would claim that this is an unjustified use
of language. We docertainly
mean something, we mean that thsi snake is sublated. But sublation is not
adequately representable in the form of a negative judgment. Sublation may
include, imply or entail a negative judgment, but it is more than that.
Even the negative judgment
that is included, implied or entailed is not of the form ['this snake is
not'], it is of the form 'no snake is here (in this), where the subject is
not [aprasakta]. It follows that the unity effected out of this and snake
through a vikalpa relation is not 'this is snake' or 'this snake', but 'sanke
is in this' or 'sanke in this ', not even 'sanke as in this' (for in the
statement 'snake as in this is not' the subject
would be equally aprasakta). We have remarked earlier that though in normal
cases 'P is in S' is translatable as 'P is as in S' this si not possible
here. The unity effected here is loose, not a close one like 'this is snake'.
It may even be said
that this unity
is little more than nominal. 'In S' in the judgment 'P is in S' does not
characterise and is not, therefore, predicable, in any normal sense of predication,
of P. The content 'snake in this' is not a unity except in name. What is
apprehended
here in [savikalpa-Pratyaksa] is the very reals snake, this and inness, and
nothing else. The factual relation is here itself the vikalpa relation.
Such is also the case with the content "hare's horn" which is
rejected in the statement "hare'shorn
is not". What is negated here is not truly "hare's horn",
but 'horn in the hare'. Such interpretation in either case may appear circuitous.
But it is inevitable, because otherwise there would be the impossible situation
that a content-'this as snake'
or "hare's horn"-is both rejected and yet a real object: If only
a content is interpreted this way the difficulty would be removed : there
would be an easy reconciliation of the rejection of a content with its being
a real object. Because there was no genuine untiy of the form 'this snake'
='this is snake' [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] takes this-aspect as belonging to thsi
rope, not to that apparent this snake. The snake that was real was not a
this snake, it was merely snake; the rope alone
was thsi rope, or, better, the rope was perceived (barely) as this. this,
only because they believed that there was a total false object of the form
'this is snake'. Why they hold this and how far they are justified will
be seen in connection withour
discussion of the [Advaita] theory of error later. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika], for
reasons we have seen, cannot subscribe to this view. According to [Nyaya-Vai'sesika],
the this-aspect does not really belong to the apparent content 'this snake'.
This does not, however, mean that the business of correction is only to
drop the this-aspect and retain the mere sanke. It is only the [Vijnanavadi
Buddhists] who argued that way and concluded that beacuse 'this' means 'to
be now outside me' correction presents the illusory content as not so outside,
and, therefore, as subjective. The [Vijnanavadin's] view has been dismissed
already. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika]
may add that correction does not drop this-aspect ; it only cancles [samanadhikaranya]
of thsi and snake and presents the illusory content as 'snake in this'.
J. Alexander's theory of error examined Alexander's theory, though largely
in tune with the [Nyaya-Vai'sesika], differs from it in an important respect.
Like the [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] thinkers, and practically on the same ground
as theirs, he too holds that this and snake are each real, and asthe
snake-as-here ('this snake') is rejected it must be a snake elsewhere. Error
lies, according to him, in mis-connecting the elsewhere snake with a sensed
this. But the main point, viz, about the exact status of the illusory content
'this snake', heleft
untouched. He draws no distinction between object and the real, except admitting
that this snake is a false appearance of the sensed rope and that the falsity
of the appearance is due to the content being a joint appearance of the rope,
on the onehand,
and the percipient mind (or the physiological organism), on the other. If
by this he means that the appearance is of the rope and yet consituted in
whatever way by the mind, it would be what we have so long been terming object.
But probably he does
not mean this. He understands it as in line with his 'mere appearance '
where the constitutive factors are all physical. His 'mere appearance' is
not object in out sense; and in false appearance it is, as appears from what
he says, an accident thatone
of the constitutive factors is the mind. Even as regards his 'real appearance',
there is no contribution of the mind. By 'appearance' he only means a selected
portion of reality. But in his doctrine of selection he errs in two ways.
In the case of
real appearance he has shown that the content of a perceptual knowledge is
a portion of the reality-con-tinuum, knowledge being nothing but a selective
response. But he does not show how 'mere appearance' is a selection. The
factors constituting it
are admittedly not
selected from the reality-continuum, but neither so is the content called
'mere appearance'. The factors, again, are parts of the reality-continuum,
though not selected ; but that content is nto even a part. It would be too
much tocontend
that the oval shape of a round coin is a part of the reality. It depends
on the position of the percipient's body vis a vis the round coin. If it
be contended that the round shape too depends on the position of the body,
the conclusion shouldrather
be that every appearance-real or mere (and a fortiori the unreal also)- depends
on the subject and is, therefore, object in our sense. There is no ground
to overlook this dependence in either case. As a matter of fact, even the
real appearace depends
on selection by the mind-depends, but for the content bring an appearance
at all. This is not to be tabooed immediately as involving ego-centric predicament.
We never deny that though the appearance so depends there is nevertheless
an independent reality
as the background, and we perceive not merely the appearance but also that
reality. If Alexander wants to avoid thsi conclusion the only course left
to him would be to hold that there is no appearance at all, but that knowledge
as diaphanous directly reveals the real. But, then, there should be no talk
of selection in the sense in which
Alexander understands the term. If reality were a continuum selection whould
change it into a definite discrete protion, and knowledge would not be diaphanous.
If, however, reality were not a continuum, but a series of discretes, knowledge
would indeed
be diaphanous, and the word 'selection' might be used in the ordinary sense
of the mind being directly in contact with one entire metaphysical structure
which Alexander had built before he turned to epistemological problems.
This is his second error.
As for the concept of diaphanous knoweldge directly referring to definite
discete reals, we have already seen its defects in Sec. I. Here we may add
one more point. If knowledge were diaphanous, directly, in contact with
definite discrete reals, how would
perception, memory, inference, etc., be distinguished from one another ?
We must say that either these cognitions are qualitatively distinct or their
contents have perceivedness in one case, rememberedness in another, inferredness
in a third, and so
on, these being emergent differential characters of the contents themselves.
But on the former alternative knowledge would no longer be diaphanous,
and the second alternative would inevitably lead to a distinction between
reality and object, that whcih
has perceivedness, rememberedness, etc., being a real, and that reality as
with the perceivedeness or rememberedness, etc., being objects. If it be
contended that the qualitative differeence of types of cognition odes not
militate against being diaphanous-each
such type directly referring to the real-we would ask: Does this nto merely
prove that there is a real (with such and such cahracters) ? From where,
then, does the consciousness of that reality as object come ? It cannot
be said that object
is another name
for there being a real. The real was there even before I knew it. Nor can
it be said that object is only another name for that real being known, for
while the 'real being known' is known as object even in the primary experience,
commonly
called introspection, the real is known as object even in the primary experience.
Knowledge as diaphanous cannot explain this primary knowledge of a real
as object. The much maligned representationism is in thsi point a better
account than directrealism.
The only defect-though that is serious- or repressentationism is that it
has very sharply distinguished object and reality to the extreme point of
their separation. They, we have so long been noting, are not separate.
Except in erroneous perception,
object cannot be dissociated from reality. Objectivity is a character accruing
to the real and is itself, on that very account, believed as real. To put
the matter more succinctly, object, except in false perception coincides
with the real. K. [Prabhakara theory of error examined like the object
of any normal perception, the false snake has to be taken as object,though
it does not coincide with the real. But this non-coincidence, we have seen,
is an anomalous phenomenon. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] tried to remove the anomaly
by recognising
the consituents only of 'this snake' as real. This, snake and the [vikalpa]
relation are alone, according to them, real; the total content is not real
an, therefore, no unitary object even. The [Prabhakaras] have proceeded
another way. They stick more closely to the basic doctrine that object (at
least in perception) must coincide with reality. Object, everywhere, is
nothing but a real as revealed by knowledge, objectivity being only the
character of being
so revealed. Because this character must belong to a real that is so revealed,
there obviously cannot be an object in default of that real. Except in cases
where a content is false or self-condtradictory, the [Naiyayika] has also
held
this view; he has excepted the false or the self-contradictory only because
it has come to be rejected. He has rather been compelled to except it.
But the [Prabhakaras] would argue that there is no such compulsion. There
is another alternative: we
may deny that the
content has at all been rejected. The [Prabhakaras] would argue as follows:
If once it is established that object is but a real as revealed by cognition
it would be senseless to modify the position to teh absurd extent that there
may be object even though it is not real. The false content is, of course,
a challenge to thsi notion
of object: it appears to be rejected in correction. But would it not be
better, the [Prabhakaras] argue, to re-assess the correction-situation to
see if that rejection is not only apparent, nothing serious, than abondoning
the definition or objectalready
established ? The [Prabhakaras] contend that in correction there is as a
matter of fact no rejection. Rejection is always of a content which was
known, i.e., taken as real object. But as in correction we come to know
that the false content was
not a real object,
this means that it was not a known object. What reflection certifies is
the true nature of a thing. Correction as reflection certifies that there
was no cognitive object. Hence truly there was no cognitive object. [Nyaya-Vai'sesika]
thinkers have also admitted this logic, though only partially. They too
have contended that because in correction we come to know that there was
no object in the form 'this snake' there really was no such object. But
immediately after this, and uncritically
enough, they have yet held that somehow they were aware of the object 'this
snake' before correction. It is because of this their uncritical faith that
they spoke of correction as the rejection (badha) of the content. The [Prabhakaras],
on the other
hand, hold that no content-not even the total content 'this snake'-is rejected.
If at all anything is rejected it is only the knowness, the cognitive character,
of the total content, the content remaining untouched. But even this cognitive
character
is not rejected. Rejection of it would imply that before correction the
content 'this snake' was apprehended as a cognitive object. Correction certifies
this much only that there was no cognitive object like 'this snake'. A cognitive
object is ipso
facto real (Paramarthika). Correction certifies only that it was not cognitive,
but conative (vyavaharika). Hence even before correction we were aware of
it as only a conative unity. This and snake were, however, cognitive and,
therefore, real object;
the question here is not about them, but about the content 'this snake'
='this snake'. But how is it, it may be asked, that when this and snake
were known as real objects the total content 'this is snake' was nto a cognitive
object ? The [Prabhakaras] reply that teh so-called total situation was,
from the cognitive point of view, a sheer
privation : we only
did nto distinguish the two cognitions-one of this and the other of snake;
or, better, the two cognitions remained undistinguished, and the so-called
unitary content, cognitively speaking, is only their non-distinction. True,
we acted
according to this so-called total content, we fled when we sae 'this snake'.
But the [Prabhakaras] argue that though such positive unitary content and
positive awareness have to be admitted the unity and the awareness are not
cognitive. 'This is snake'
is, in other words, no object. It is either what is only referred to by
conation or a mere verbal unity. Two things non-distinguished are often
taken as one unity in the context of an act. It is the act which treats
tham as though they are unified. Act or will is normally indeed a response
to a cognitive unity. But even in every such normal act there are
contents which are cognised as non-distinct and yet unified by that act.
What is called object of will is primarily the object of the cognition that
causes the will; but in every will there is inevitably reference also to
the means and a purpose which
do not stand cognised
as related to that object or to one another. By 'purpose' here is meant
the actualisation (bhavana) of the object. The object of will was cognised
as only a future reality, but there was no cognition of it as to be actualised.
Futurity
of the object was no doubt cognised, but it means only future actuality,
not the dynamic to be actualised which is a peculiar unification, through
will only, of the object and its futurity. X, Y, Z which are means to that
actualisation were also
cognised, but not
as means. Their means hood (upayata) is another peculiar unification, by
will only, of X, Y, Z with that object of will. They might have been cognised
as causes, but not as means. Means-hodd and purpose-hood are absolutely
conativecategories.
Action alone thus unifies contents which are cognised as non-distinct, e.i.,
unrelated to one another, relation necessarily presupposing that relata are
known as distinct from one another. We have seen that the contents of [nirvikalpa-Pratyaksa]
in [Nyaya-Vai'sesika] were also known as non-distinct from one another, 'non-distinct'
meaning here, as also in the [Prabhakara] view under discussion, not that
the contents are each known with its self-identity, but that they are not
known as each being
not another or each dissociated from another. We have also seen how in [savikalpa-Pratyaksa]
these non-distinct contents get related to one another and turn into a unity
(though these relations and that unity are not merely subjective). Such
unity
is cognitive. The [Prabhakaras] only contend that there is also anothere
type of unity which, as described above, is conative. The conative unity
is called by them [vyavaharika]. As in normal will, so also in illusion
the unity 'this snake' is [vyavaharika]
only. This and snake get unified in the context of act only. There is another
possible account of the positive unity of the illusory content, and some
[Prabhakaras] have admitted that. It is that the unity is only verbal.
In a sense the [Naiyayikas] also regard the unity, not only here but even
in normal [savikalpa-Pratyaksa],
as verbal. Every [savikalpa-Pratyaksa] is, according to them, ['sabdanubiddha].
[Vikalpa] relations are necessarily semantic forms of language, forms
of language as judgement. The language that is is dissociated from of language
spoken,
not heard, language that is spoken being, as spoken, undissociable from knowledge
as judgment. The language that is dissociated from knowledge as judgment
is the language which is heard, such language as heard being taken as a system
of sounds or marks
producing in the hearer another judgmental knowledge which, however, is not
then spoken by the hearer implicitly or explicitly. The unity, thus, not
merely in illusion but in every case of [savikalpa-Pratyaksa] is , according
to the [Naiyayika], verbal.
But the [Naiyaika] has not refrained from saying that as much in illusion
as in every case of [savikalpa-pratyaksa] it is also read and, therefore,
an object. These [Prabhakaras], however, here part company. They agree
with the [Naiyaikas] that
in normal [savikalpa-pratyaksa]
the unity is an object and would even go farther and hold that there is such
unity as object even in [nirvikalpa-Pratyaksa] where it remains in some latent
form. But they would entirely disagree with them so far as the content
of erroneous perception is concerned. The unitary content is in this case
merely verbal, not real. Whichever way 'this snake' is interpreted-whether
as non-distinction of thsi and snake or as a conative or a merely verbal
unity of these there is no question of its rejection. What may be said to
be rejected is only the positive cognitive character of
'this snake'. But,
as already seen, even this is not rejected, we only deny it. Even before
correction 'this snake' was not apprehended as a possitive cognitive object.
The [Prabhakara] view is in perfect consonance with the doctrine that every
cognitive object is real. But its weakness also is evident, and the weakness
is fundamental. The [Prabhakara] contention that even the cognitive character
of the object 'this snake' is not rejected, but only negated, does not appear
to be a sound account of the business of correction. Whatever be the [Prabhakara]
theory, we do feel that before
correction we were
aware fo 'this snake' as a cognitive object. It is too much to claim that
we were aware of it as a conative or only a verbal object or as this and
snake non-distinguished. The [Prabhakaras] were right in claiming that reflection
offers
a true account of the nature of the thing reflected on. But this does not
mean that even before reflection we were aware of the thing in that correct
way. Often the reflective account appears, without any hitch, as contradicting
and often, again,
as rejecting the
unreflective account. There is no good reason why the [Prabhakaras] should
discount the second contingency. Rejection (badha) is often an actual phenomenon,
and it is no good fighting shy of it. But once we admit rejection it would